Book Read Free

Young William James Thinking

Page 29

by Paul J Croce


  experience of his 1860s hope to generate faith that some vocational results

  would emerge from his daily searching work: “[E]ven when you seem to

  yourself to be making no pro gress, . . . if you but go on in your own uninter-

  esting way they must bloom out in their good time.” Just as the later essay

  was not simply advice to create beliefs wholesale, so his youthful urge to

  reduce worry about results did not ignore physical factors and tangible

  constraints, nor blithely reject planning for future vocational directions.

  Instead, letting results float up spurred his motivation to face the future

  despite pres ent discouragements— and even to work within them— because

  it “gave me a willingness to work where I saw no object to be gained.” This

  outlook, he reported, had a “potent effect in my inner life.” Even when he

  had little yet to show for it, he felt confident that in time “the result would

  come up as it were of its own accord.” When writing to his fellow student of

  physiology, Henry Bowditch, he offered the solace that, “however discour-

  aging the work of each day may seem, stick at it long enough, and you’ll

  wake up some morning,— a physiologist.” In Princi ples of Psy chol ogy (1890),

  James virtually quotes his private writing of twenty- two years earlier: “Let

  no youth have any anxiety about the upshot of his education. . . . If he keep

  faithfully busy each hour of the working day, he may safely leave the final

  result to itself.” Before he had a label for it or details of argumentation to

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  161

  describe it, young James had developed his own private will to believe in

  the vocational path he was on, even though he had few results yet in evi-

  dence. Already in the 1860s, his nascent theory provided a way to cope with

  limited knowledge and ambiguity, and this posture would allow him to act

  with purpose, a teleological orientation, but without the expectation of

  prior or ideal goals guiding that purpose. His would be a future- oriented

  teleology because those results and that purpose would be in a future still

  in the making, a usable theory for young James.47 He could not escape being

  reflective, so he turned to reflective solutions for the prob lems of reflection.

  While speculating about his personal direction, James focused on a key

  ele ment for his goal: “[A]ll moral action, of course, even if its direction be

  distorted shows the possibility of Freedom.” Such freedom would allow for

  working toward the future with deliberate choices along the way rather

  than by following fixed goals. But it was one thing to counsel others about

  letting results float up; how could he summon his own spirit of freedom

  when he felt so burdened by indecision, theoretical confusion, vocational

  constraints, and health prob lems? In his private writing, his mind raced

  ahead of his current circumstances as he hoped for decisive action despite

  the immediate burdens of his current fate. These constraints on his free-

  dom had created, as he said with studied understatement, his gap “between

  Will and per for mance.” He used German words to amplify his points:

  “[T]he shall (sollen), . . . in the shape of fate [including] moral or natu ral law,

  is to the individual . . . despotic & oppressive,” because “the person, considered

  f[ro]m. the side of . . . shall, is limited, determined to a par tic u lar course.”

  By contrast, the willful choices based on individual intentions (associated

  with the German word wol en) can potentially bring freedom from fate, since

  “the person [who] wills is unlimited.” His attention to will was not, however,

  as yet very liberating in practice since these thoughts reminded him of his

  reflections on Hamlet as an example of a modern character struggling with

  “an inadequate will,” just like his own. His inquiries about German words

  and the Danish prince reminded him of the weakness of his own will even

  as he longingly admired the significance of volition’s power in theory.

  Through advice to friends, and to himself, he had set up his goal, still on

  theoretical grounds, for acting with will, first by focusing on small daily

  steps and letting go of expectations for results. However, as long as his will

  remained weak, his admiration for volitional power would leave him as just

  another modern case of mere longing— with a deci ded “disproportion . . . be-

  tween Will & per for mance. ”48 James could only apply his theory of will

  162  Young William James Thinking

  once he could overcome his own Hamlet prob lem. He could not just talk

  himself into a strong will; already showing his philosophical inclinations,

  reflective James needed a framework to justify its role.

  The Stoic Will within the Vast Machinery of the World

  In his admiring glances at the ancients, James reached for their inspira-

  tions but found them difficult to grasp. The natu ral grace of Greek art pro-

  vided models for living comfortably with natu ral experiences that would

  enable action without worry, but without a practical framework, he could

  not find a way to achieve this stance, until he discovered the ancient phi-

  losophy of Stoicism. Its advocates posited divine immanence in the world

  with proposals to adjust personal lives to the order of nature—in par tic u lar,

  Stoics urged contentment with things that could not be changed. This an-

  cient philosophy served effectively as a major religious orientation in the

  Greco- Roman world during the centuries before and after the birth of Je-

  sus. Stoic insights complemented the spiritual message James found in Greek

  art. Without seeking transcendental redemption, the Stoic goal, as James

  noticed, was to live “a life in which your individual will becomes so harmo-

  nized to nature’s will” that you “cheerfully . . . acquiesce in what ever she

  assigns to you.” He did not yet know his own vocational or personal pur-

  pose, but he admired the Stoic proposal to quell the longing, “knowing that

  you serve some purpose in her vast machinery wh[ich]. will never be revealed

  to you.” 49 Proposing willful commitment despite uncertainties, Stoicism

  spoke directly to James’s chief concerns in the 1860s.

  James’s first known encounter with Stoicism was in 1863, when he re-

  corded pithy insights of Epictetus, a Greek sage living in Rome from the late

  first to second century ce. The Stoic phi los o pher lived in simplicity, early on

  literally as a slave in Rome, and then, with few possessions, as a teacher

  without even writing down his thoughts. His students eagerly recorded his

  teachings, although he himself had little concern for publication or posterity,

  because his passion was for philosophy as a guide to life. We have no power

  over the world’s impact on us, he insisted in his power ful oral discourses, but

  “we, not externals, are the masters of our judgments.” James became an

  eager student of Epictetus as well, recording many of his teachings in a

  notebook also containing notes on the evolution of ancient religions, mod-

  ern theories of scientific materialism, and Christian theology. James indi-

  cated his understanding of the person
al uses that Stoics made for philo-

  sophical reflection when he paraphrased Epictetus’s recommendation that

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  163

  a phi los o pher’s “first card should be the ease and quiet of his own breast.”

  The young science student found inspiration for his emerging resolution

  not to worry about results in Epictetus’s advice that it would be “a less evil

  for you that your servant or child should be vicious than that you your self

  should be perpetually unhappy with an anxious care to prevent it.” James

  took to heart Epictetus’s prediction that “I am in his power who can gratify

  my wishes and inflict my fears,” as he was trying to strengthen his will to

  fortify his own direction in life. 50

  Some of Epictetus’s words that James recorded had par tic u lar resonance

  in the early 1860s; Epictetus had lived as a slave, physically in the power of

  others, but he spoke of a form of slavery beyond legal title: “Not to be a slave

  then, I must have neither Desire nor aversion for anything in the power of

  others.” While clearly not as severe as chattel slavery, such psychological

  slavery from giving up one’s own thoughts and feelings also brought a ser-

  vile posture with passive subordination to another’s will. In the antislavery

  James family, younger brothers Wilkie and Bob worked against the Ameri-

  can institution of slavery itself, and William, more like his father, portrayed

  the intellectual burdens of slavery. When he recorded the words of Epicte-

  tus in 1863, the Northern war purpose was turning toward abolition of

  slavery; William James did not serve in the war, but he shows his affiliation

  with the in de pen dent spirit of the free- labor ideology that would dominate

  the Union cause, here expressed in the stringent terms of Stoic self-

  understanding: “[D]espise . . . every thing out of your own power.” The Ameri-

  can version of this focus on personal power spurred the military push for

  total war against the power of slaveholders and fostered the African Ameri-

  can quest for personal liberty, and it would encourage the private initiative

  of American capitalism. 51 Young James’s version of this ideology, expressed

  in the accent of ancient philosophy, was for personal direction; Stoicism

  would help him develop the power of his will.

  When James returned in 1866 from his natu ral history expedition in

  Brazil to resume the study of medicine, he was again attracted to Stoicism.

  His brother Henry pointed out, in a review of a recent edition of Epictetus,

  that Stoicism was a philosophy that was “in effect not a philosophy” but a

  set of insights fostering the view that one’s “attitude of mind was a refuge”;

  Henry held out par tic u lar praise for Marcus Aurelius, a student of Epicte-

  tus. That same year, William James “began . . . to read the thoughts of the

  Roman Stoic Marcus Aurelius.” James even spoke of Marcus’s Meditations

  as if it were good medicine, with doses of it taken slowly and deliberately,

  164  Young William James Thinking

  “two or three pages a day.” He was already thinking about the themes he

  would state with admiration about the Greeks in his diary two years later:

  Marcus Aurelius “certainly had an invincible soul” because he lived a “life

  according to nature.” During this season when the Civil War was still a

  fresh memory, James enlisted the Stoic philosophy to address his commit-

  ment to philanthropic purpose in almost military terms: “The stoic feeling

  of being a sentinel obeying orders without knowing the General’s plans is a

  noble one.” The Stoic “General” was fate, and James’s “sentinel” position

  was scientific study. Even before starting his studies, he had already de-

  clared, “I want . . . to do some good, no matter what” with science. Now he

  was training to make that hope real, and Stoicism gave him a framework for

  understanding that, when “I make my nick” in some vocational contribu-

  tion whether large or small, this would be the way to “assert my real ity.” He

  wrote to his friend Ward urging the Stoic outlook with words that also

  served as advice to himself: “I think old Mark’s perpetual yearnings for pa-

  tience and equanimity & kindliness w[oul]d. do your heart good.” Marcus’s

  message was to live life “easily & patiently, without feeling responsible for

  [the] future.” While James still did not know which career he would take

  up, the ancient perspective as reinforced by Stoic philosophy was helping

  him to realize that these uncertainties were not some burden to be over-

  come; instead, his path could itself become the goal. Inspired by Stoicism,

  he would continue his daily tasks, namely learning human physiology with

  excursions into philosophy; such efforts, “no matter . . . his lot in life,” as the

  Stoics asserted, would “be a pleasing spectacle.” These ancient inspirations

  gave him “a pretty practical contentment,” even though “I cannot help feel-

  ing as if I were insulting Heaven.” 52 He realized that his reflections were

  taking him beyond the religious mainstream.

  These ideas could well seem like an insult to mainstream American

  Chris tian ity. Stoicism was founded in Athens three hundred years before

  Jesus; although Marcus Aurelius lived more than a century after the inau-

  guration of the Common Era marked by the birth of Jesus, he felt almost no

  impact from Chris tian ity, since this fast- growing religion from Palestine

  was still a marginal movement within the Roman Empire in 121 ce when

  Marcus was born. The Greek phi los o pher Zeno of Citium, who first devel-

  oped Stoicism, came of age shortly after the reign of Alexander the Great,

  whose fierce conquests also created cosmopolitan mingling of cultures. Zeno

  took worldly existence as the context for his program of moral action; and in

  the chaos of the social changes around him, he advocated personal disci-

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  165

  pline to find happiness by remaining steadfast to one’s internal state no

  matter what was happening all around. Cicero in first- century ce Rome

  was instrumental in disseminating Stoicism in the Roman Empire, where

  its outlooks reinforced popu lar Roman virtues. Marcus encountered Sto-

  icism from travel to Greece during one of his military campaigns and still

  more deeply through the teachings of his teacher, Epictetus. 53

  At the core of Stoicism was a belief that every thing exists from the power

  of and in conformity with universal Nature, also named with words that

  can be translated as Reason, Log os, Destiny, Creative Fire, God, Providence,

  Soul of the World, or just the All. This spiritual power in the universe was

  infinite in space and time, like a set of rational laws of development, or con-

  ditions of all existence; although this power was not personal, that did not

  displace discussion of the gods, especially Zeus. The Stoics approached the

  gods as did most Greeks, as the personal repre sen ta tion of abstract forces of

  nature. References to Zeus or translations of the All as God were particu-

  larly popu lar in the Christian era because they contributed to a perception


  that Stoicism was not incompatible with Chris tian ity or was even a historical

  stage toward the religion of Jesus Christ. Emphasizing the interpretation of

  pre- Christian sensibilities anxious because of their lack of transcendent

  references, Matthew Arnold even presented “Marcus Aurelius . . . agitated,

  stretching out his arms for something beyond.” Stoicism did in fact influ-

  ence Chris tian ity, especially in standards of morality and in re spect for the

  individual. 54 However, Stoicism was decidedly unlike Chris tian ity in its com-

  patibility with polytheism and its commitment to an immanent spiritual

  force, distinct from a transcendent and mono the istic God.

  The Stoic philosophy had three aspects: physics, logic, and ethics. These

  could be separated only for teaching and learning; in life, they intermingled

  seamlessly. Physics dealt not only with the view of physical things themselves

  but also with the structure of the cosmos that housed them, somewhat like

  modern theology. Because Reason pervaded the world, it was immanent in

  matter, imparting harmony in all parts and within the whole— just what

  James detected in Greek sculpture. “This mutual integration is a universal

  princi ple,” as Marcus put it, adding that “a myriad of causes combine into

  the single Cause which is destiny.” This singleness was not a personal being

  but the action of “all things . . . with one movement,” each serving as the

  “cooperating cause . . . of all” in the “structure of the web.” There was no

  absolute distinction between Reason and the rest of the universe; Reason

  was simply the most cohesive and creative component— and humanity’s

  166  Young William James Thinking

  path for understanding. The Soul of the World sustained and pervaded all

  things, which contained the creative fire in degrees: inanimate things with

  the least; plants with more; and animals with still more in their rudimentary

  ability to reason; with their rational capacity, humans bear some similar-

  ity to the Soul of the World itself. Marcus described it as “that inward di-

  vinity, that particle of himself, which Zeus has given to every man.” The

  human ability to reason suggested the second aspect of Stoic philosophy,

  logic, which referred to the rules for finding truth. Rigorous truth claims

 

‹ Prev