Book Read Free

Young William James Thinking

Page 30

by Paul J Croce


  were impor tant to ensure the coherence of judgments, and philosophical

  use of Reason was the way to “establish what is true.” The Stoics argued for

  the existence of the divine because, if something exists that is more com-

  plex than the capacity of the human mind, this must have emerged from

  reasoning that surpasses the human. 55

  Physics and logic were essential factors in the makeup of their ethics, the

  third and most impor tant ele ment of their philosophy. This was especially

  true of the Roman Stoics, and Marcus in par tic u lar emphasized personal

  discipline and character development in his commitment to Stoicism. Their

  ethics was built on the Stoic attention to Reason; this awesome immanent

  force gives humans the ability to reflect about and analyze the world around

  them and to make free choices. This capacity lifts humans above the tan-

  gled and mysterious vicissitudes of life and into the distinctive realm gov-

  erned by human volition. 56 The world’s destiny operates by chance forces

  that are beyond human comprehension, only fully understandable from the

  perspective of the All. That comprehensive perspective is ever out of reach

  of human understanding or control, but our will is a precious island in the

  All, the only spot removed from this sea of chance. James was drawn to

  both the Stoic cosmic picture of Reason in the world and the commanding

  role for the will in human life.

  From this picture, the Stoics developed their central ethical dictum, a

  fundamental distinction between what does and what does not depend on

  human power. We cannot control the direction of the world and most of

  what happens to us, but we can control our own wills. This fire within de-

  fines the self, and with enough discipline, it is an almost impregnable for-

  tress; it is also a gatekeeper since the will controls what enters the mind. The

  Stoics had a very bald, uncomplicated view of this psychological pro cess:

  they advocated adopting only adequate or objective mental repre sen ta tions,

  ones that, from their perspective, correspond directly to real ity. Their point

  was to emphasize peering directly at objects and events in the world by

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  167

  “penetrating into them and exposing their real nature,” as opposed to look-

  ing at them with perceptions clouded by our hopes and personal values,

  which inevitably bring false judgments. Taking a perception of something

  as it is and stripping it of the “cloak of verbiage that dignifies it” will bring a

  direct grasp of real ity; while this approach can seem naïve by comparison

  with modern psychological views of under lying motivations and skepticism

  about objectivity, it also has a robust experiential directness: put aside

  wishful expectations that distract from the main course of events. They ex-

  pressed these ideas with blunt bodily statements that would have appealed

  to James’s eagerness to understand the role of physiology within psy chol-

  ogy and spirituality; for example, Epictetus asserted that “you are nothing

  but a little soul carry ing a cadaver. ”57 While physical facts set limits, the

  Stoics pointed beyond material constraints to the personal will that orches-

  trated the other wise powerless body.

  With this standard for real ity in natu ral facts, and the advice to be con-

  cerned only with what we can control, the Stoics proposed that it is not

  things that trou ble us but only our judgments or repre sen ta tions of them—or,

  really, our illusions: most people are weighed down by feelings of longing,

  regret, or frustration, even though these are the very parts of the situation

  that we can control. From this outlook flowed the well- known Stoic view

  that we should be happy with the pres ent and not expend useless thoughts

  on what is beyond our grasp, since such striving will simply result in fruit-

  less worry and wasted effort. An upshot of this was that the Stoics advocated

  finding contentment in life, no matter one’s material condition, even to the

  point of physical suffering. If the condition was really beyond one’s control, it

  should be treated with indifference; if not, Epictetus observed, “I make a

  slave of myself” to the things out of reach. However, living life within the

  limits of one’s own control, with full recognition of human finitude, could

  give mere mortals the opportunity to live a godlike existence, with abso-

  lute control over their own domains. This liberating tough- mindedness

  also gave Stoicism a reputation for sternness; but despite the proverbial

  “stoical” attitudes toward suffering, the phi los o phers themselves adopted

  this posture not in resignation but with a drive to serve humanity. This

  riveted attention to dignity within each person prompted the Stoics to pro-

  duce some of the first philosophical commitments to universal re spect for

  the human worth of all people no matter their condition; from Zeno’s ini-

  tial impulses to find serenity in chaos, the Stoics strug gled against injus-

  tices, which are, in effect, the world’s lack of serenity. 58

  168  Young William James Thinking

  For the Stoics, the point of doing philosophy was not to construct refined

  arguments or even to have anything written down. Instead, philosophy was

  a practical tool for guiding one’s life. As Martha Nussbaum has pointed out,

  Stoicism was among the Hellenistic theories that had medical conceptions

  of the philosophic vocation: argumentation would serve as therapy for iden-

  tification of the diseases of belief and judgment that plague mankind and

  would foster guidance through the thoughts and actions that will heal those

  diseased perceptions; James read daily doses of Marcus Aurelius in just this

  spirit, and while he was studying medicine no less. Cicero called Stoic phi-

  losophy “a medical art for the soul,” and with this intellectual therapy, we are

  “capable of doctoring ourselves.” Marcus had first become attracted to the

  moral toughness and personal commitment of the Stoic outlook in his youth,

  and he converted during his twenty- fifth year. He became especially devoted

  to this guiding outlook during his reign as emperor, which began fifteen

  years later in 161 ce; although he enjoyed the privileges of power, the weighty

  responsibilities of his position also felt like a prison. The duties were par-

  ticularly difficult because this was a time when Rome was enduring early

  phases of severe challenge to its vast geographic reach. He wrote the Medi-

  tations in Greek, in the tradition of hypomnēmata, or personal notes, in or-

  der to keep his philosophical bearings during the turmoil of his reign; in

  fact, he wrote the notes that make the book while on a military campaign in

  170–180 ce in con temporary Serbia and Hungary—in other words, he wrote

  for himself while far from home and under duress. He never intended pub-

  lication, and he did not even include a title. Over the centuries, these notes

  have been printed in many editions with many titles, each pointing to as-

  pects of his purpose in writing: “On His Life,” “Moral Life,” “On the Duty of

  Life,” “Notes Which He Wrote for Himself,”
“About Himself to Himself,”

  “Paths toward Himself,” or simply “To Myself”; and a translation under its

  more familiar title even became a bestseller in 2002. Marcus gave “proof of

  his learning,” as ancient historian Herodian said in appreciation of Stoic

  goals, by the “temperate way of life” that he presented with transparent

  simplicity. The text provided James with a model for coping with his own

  challenges.59

  The lived philosophy and practical purposes of the Meditations explain

  several striking features of the emperor’s reflective work, including its lack

  of any special order, its continuous repetitions, and its frequent use of quo-

  tations. These were part of Marcus’s deliberate efforts to control his inner

  discourse for self- persuasion in order to fulfill the Stoic dictum to distinguish

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  169

  what he could influence from what he could not. These hastily composed

  notes— and they almost certainly remained that way until after Marcus’s death,

  when his supporters edited them for public distribution— bear some similar-

  ity to James’s diary entries; both works were personal notes, unselfconscious,

  unpolished, and not intended for publication, but they have flashes of deep

  insight, and they were each the recordings of deeply reflective men trying

  to muster and maintain a philosophy of life that would serve as a guide in

  a sea of turmoil— albeit in very diff er ent settings. The timing of James’s

  reading of the Meditations and the similarly reflective character of his di-

  ary entries on the ancients suggest that he may have been influenced in

  the composition of his notes by Marcus’s method itself. James even used

  Marcus’s approach to philosophy as a kind of inner citadel for personal

  striving: by 1870, when James was particularly discouraged about his pros-

  pects, he wrote, “[I]n that inner solitary room of communion with his own

  good will, there lies for every man comfort”— and there also lies the site for

  “battling with misfortune. ”60 He certainly admired the ancient Roman, and

  he would have known that, for a Stoic, writing directional thoughts to one-

  self would be part and parcel of philosophy as a way of life, not just as ab-

  stract theorizing. The Stoic willingness to regard the work of philosophy as

  a means for treating unhealthy frames of mind served James as edifying

  personal therapy, much like his use of alternative medical therapies.

  James’s admiration for Stoic philosophy continued to appear in his pri-

  vate and public writings. He sometimes referred to its ideas, especially about

  the will’s inner citadel, without even mentioning Stoic names. For example,

  shortly after arriving in Germany during the fall of 1867, he paused from his

  study of psy chol ogy to read lit er a ture, which inspired a spirit of “compro-

  mise with the nature of things.” When he was back home in 1869 studying

  for his medical degree, he wrote to his friend Henry Bowditch with ex-

  tended worries about the small amount of studying he was able to do. Then

  he stopped himself short with the comment, “I’ve done what I can, and it[’]s

  a mean thing for a man to fret, about what is accidentally & externally

  imposed on him.” Whether or not James’s trou bles were fully imposed ex-

  ternally, Epictetus or Marcus could not have better expressed the need to

  resign oneself to things beyond one’s control. A few years later, after his

  darkest discouragements, James even remembered the ancients at a light

  moment, in admiration for the family dog for his “roman firmness and in de-

  pen dence of his character.” Toward the end of his life, he gave Marcus’s

  Meditations as a gift, declaring its Stoic outlooks “creditable to human nature”

  170  Young William James Thinking

  and full of “comfort in extreme old age. ”61 From daily life to the deepest of

  reflections, James’s youthful inspirations from Stoicism would remain a

  constant touchstone. This ancient philosophy, with worldly settings for im-

  material forces, would supply him with encouragement for his own will to

  believe before he would develop the theory: Stoicism brought the edifying

  demand to stand with the power of his will even when burdened by impos-

  ing constraints.

  The Ancient Dispensation and Prospects

  for Finite Absoluteness

  As William James became established in his personal life and in his career,

  he made fewer references to the ancients. In 1873 he applied his character-

  istic ambivalence to his youthful fascination: “It’s the most idiotic thing in

  the world to say on[e] thing about either antiquity or civilization.” And yet

  his interest in the ancients persisted, dispersing into his later thoughts. By

  the mid-1870s, he was already acting on many of the insights he had gleaned

  from the ancients, and he was weighing the characteristics of both ancient

  and modern times for construction of his own decisive integration of their

  messages. Rather that choosing one correct outlook, he learned from each;

  he found a deep paradoxical significance in diverse and even clashing views:

  “[N]othing is true unless with the admission that its opposite is also true.”

  The ancients would become major factors within his convictions about the

  importance of mediating contrasts and avoiding generalized abstractions,

  both as one perspective among others and for their tolerant messages them-

  selves. Even at the peak of his youthful interest, he had not fully adopted

  ancient views, and then as his interests dissipated, the attractions of his

  youth remained a touchstone for much of his thinking. British phi los o pher

  F. H. Bradley called the religious strands of James’s mature philosophy “good

  Stoicism,” and James himself occasionally referred to his commitment to the

  will as “my stoicism”; but he chaffed at the “hardness” of this ancient out-

  look, “which sometimes oppresses me. ”62 Despite the appeal of Stoicism, he

  searched for more.

  James balanced his admiration for Stoic views of nature and the sturdi-

  ness of the human will with critiques about why Stoicism did not endure

  beyond ancient times, and even with some sharply worded denigration. In

  his psychological texts of the 1890s, James identified the Stoic readiness to

  “dispossess yourself . . . of all that was out of your own power” as a way to

  illustrate the profile of rather “unsympathetic characters” who “retract . . .

  The Ancient Art of Natu ral Grace  171

  their Me,” a position that generates a “definiteness in the outline” of the self

  as consolation “for the smallness of its content.” But he also acknowl-

  edged that this resolve gave the Stoics heroic courage “without fear”

  even to face one’s own death. In The Va ri e ties of Religious Experience (1902),

  James gave psychological expression to the mainstream historical interpre-

  tation that the ancient Greeks and Romans “knew no joys comparable in

  quality of preciousness” with those of “twice- born people whose religion is

  non- naturalistic,” born again to transcendent forces much loftier than

  those of the h
ere and now. Citing religions with such “renunciation” of

  merely earthly existence, he also went beyond the mainstream in referring

  to these twice- born commitments held not only by Christians but also by

  “Brahmans, Buddhists, . . . and Mohammedans.” By contrast, the “con-

  sciousness [of the] Greek or Roman . . . even in Homeric times was full to

  the brim” with “sad mortality” from being only once- born creatures of “this

  sunlit world.” Despite all their august achievements, the ancients could of-

  fer no hope for “another and a better world. ”63 Yet their focus on depths of

  meaning in nature provided a resource for his program of future science, in

  critique of scientific tendencies to reduce experience to material forces.

  James’s attraction to the ancient views of nature provided ways to cope

  with his simultaneous re spect for science and curiosity about the role of im-

  material forces in life. He envied the ancients’ absence of longing, and he

  relished the German romantic writer Friedrich Schiller’s characterization

  of the naïve yet graceful posture of the ancients; but he was fully aware that

  these perspectives had been eclipsed with the growing authority of modern

  science and even since ancient times after religions of transcendence had

  come to dominate. James admired mainstream religions not with full en-

  dorsement but with respectful acknowl edgment of their deep human appeal.

  In the 1870s, he called his posture an “attitude . . . of deference rather than of

  adoption,” but from “sheer stress,” he himself was sometimes attracted to

  such religious assurance, even if not as “an everyday comfort.” While the

  great faiths generally offered absolute convictions with renunciation of na-

  ture, James himself was more attracted to the attitude of the ancients, who

  had a cosmopolitan tolerance of diff er ent beliefs and a spirituality of nature.

  In 1869 his cousin and good friend Mary (or Minny) Temple said even

  more sharply what James was already feeling: institutional religions clearly

  appealed to many with “the ‘remote possibility’ of the best thing”— namely,

  the glory of redemption into a transcendent afterlife. Temple, a self-

  professed modern “pagan,” was willing to “put . . . up with the second- best,”

  172  Young William James Thinking

 

‹ Prev